This article builds on several previous essays. You will find the latest versions of all the currently available articles in this series at the website, “From Mechanism to a Science of Qualities”. By clicking on the shaded rectangles at the end of many scientific terms, you can immediately read a definition of the terms in a separate glossary window (or tab, if your browser is set that way).
For more than two centuries biologists have struggled to find an elusive pathway between the lifelessness of inanimate nature and what they feared as the supernatural, mystical, or vitalistic excess easily induced in weak, sentimental observers by an overly close, personal attention to actual living creatures.
As a convinced materialist, the biologist prefers to model the organism as nothing more than an improbably differentiated and well-crafted mass of law-abiding physical substance. (The materials in the human body, as the old saying went, have a market value of about 97 cents — before adjusting for inflation.) Such a mass, of course, is receptive to all those “mechanistic explanations” we ceaselessly encounter in the technical literature. The only problem is that, however intricately assembled, a lump of earth is not very convincing at sustaining a pretense of life.
But on the other hand, we hear the actual organism faithfully described as a striving, intending, cognitively shrewd creature through and through. It senses its environment, responds intelligently according to its own needs, maintains homeostasis, has become a crafty expert at surviving and reproducing, and knows exactly when to feign altruism in its own interest (or the interest of its genes). The fly in the ointment here is that such a self-possessed being of subtle insight and well-directed initiative seems almost preternatural — too alive for a materialistic biology still obsessed with the real or imagined sins of the vitalists.
The solution to both the lack of vitality and the excess of it has proven
effective beyond all hopes. First we educate the earthen mass by
investing a subset of its molecules —
The great advantage of programmatic information is that it can seem to rival Solomon’s sagacity while at the same time lying low and disguising itself as “dumb matter”. And so, in this age of information and computers, the materialist has learned to breathe freely at last. “There is no spirit-driven life force”, proclaimed Richard Dawkins with an almost audible sigh of relief, “no throbbing, heaving, pullulating, protoplasmic, mystic jelly. Life is just bytes and bytes and bytes of digital information” (1995, pp. 18-19).
But perhaps we should take a look for ourselves.
Suppose a
How, in reality, might we assess the significance of the change for the
organism? (You will recall from biology class that DNA can serve as a
kind of template for
Our single mutated letter, as it happens, may exert its influences (and in
turn be influenced) in remarkably diverse ways. It might, for example,
raise or lower the melting temperature of its local stretch of DNA
— the temperature at which the two strands of the DNA double helix
disengage from each other — thereby making transcription easier or
more difficult at that location. Or it might contribute toward a more or
less bendable DNA
All such effects of our mutation can have dramatic implications for gene
expression. And they can also influence yet higher-order structural
features that bear on expression. For example, by contributing to an
anchoring sequence for a particular protein known as “CTCF”, a single base
change can modulate the way a chromosome segment loops dynamically through
the cell nucleus, bringing nearby or distant segments of the chromosome
together according to their need for interaction. Or it might add its own
influence to the various forces and factors determining how entire
chromosomes are disposed spatially in the nucleus — a spatial
distribution that relates to
In other words (as so many technical papers emphasize today): genes must find their places within the ever-changing, three-dimensional, spatiotemporal order of the nucleus in order to contribute their part to the current needs of the organism. And any base change can modulate this well-choreographed performance of the larger nucleus.
There’s also the whole matter of DNA repair and rearrangement. Depending
on circumstances, the mutation might trigger one of the DNA damage
response pathways, and this could lead to a “correction” of the
mutation. But it could also lead to a more radical remodeling of the DNA
around the mutation. Moreover, if the mutation occurs in a germline cell,
it could transform one of many cryptic
Classically, the geneticist would have asked first of all about the
effects of our mutation either upon a
None of this vast wealth of expressive potential looks very much like the
kind of thing that might be specified by the approximately two “yes-or-no”
Part of the problem is that DNA can undergo conformational changes that distort the classical double helix. The resulting variations in the way that DNA bases are presented to proteins can thus affect the recognition mechanism . . . Protein–DNA binding is still commonly thought of purely in terms ofcodes and sequencemotifs, rather than as thebinding of two large macromolecules that have complex shapes and considerable conformational flexibility. (Honig and Rohs 2011)
In reality, everything is a matter of shape and transformation.
This is equally true of that other premier “informational molecule”,
A one-dimensional code is giving way to the infinite expressive potentials of dynamic spatial form changing with time. The molecules of our cells dance their way through life rather than yielding to the militaristic rigidity of fixed codes.
It is well to picture as concretely as possible the intentional molecular
communities engaged in
And why should the molecules not wander “off-topic”? Such undirected behavior is, in fact, the rule for those same molecules when they move about in a decaying corpse rather than a living organism. It is not, after all, the business of molecules, understood solely in terms of physical law, to “know” what their task should be here and now, as opposed to there and later. It is not their business to pay attention to the needs of anyone or anything. Yet such needs and such attention are exactly what the biologist is continually tracing.
All this should remind us of something almost never alluded to in the workaday literature: there are two very different sorts of description or explanation, only one of which is distinctively biological. Nearly everything about gene expression described above implies a kind of implicit cognitive functioning of the cell. Call it “biological wisdom” if you wish. In any case, what we see is intentional aim and well-timed coordination; it’s a matter of getting a job done correctly in light of the particular challenges and needs of the moment. Biological description is always of this sort. It’s full of the kind of meaning we find in storytelling — something I pointed out at length in “How Biologists Lost Sight of the Meaning of Life”.
But we also necessarily look at these same processes through the eyes of the physicist and chemist. Their eyes dare not see molecules pursuing aims or molecular interactions shaped by challenges and needs. At the inorganic level we observe processes lacking what is usually referred to as teleology (goal-directedness). We have learned not to look here for intentions, plans, or purposes, whether explicit (conscious) or otherwise. Rocks do not intend to roll downhill. This is why a science of the inorganic never gives us biological explanation as such.
The biological reason for characterizing the strictly physical and chemical processes of the organism is so that, taking up a higher perspective from which we can survey those processes together, we can begin to recognize in them patterns of coordination and intention — patterns the physicist and chemist could never see while remaining within the cause-and-effect terms of their own disciplines. Only so do we begin to apprehend an organism’s life, rather than the more universal lawfulness we might call its “corpse-potential”. (For more on these two kinds of description, see the earlier article in this series, “What Do Organisms Mean?”)
Whether or not biologists have adequately reckoned with — or even recognized — the problems posed by the two different sorts of description, they have instinctively responded by embracing information-processing machines as models for understanding organisms. For, in its own way, the humanly programmed computer also submits to two levels of description. It combines unimpeded physical lawfulness with cognitively informed patterns of activity.
That is exactly the combination the biologist needs. The problem is that, as models of organisms, computers display almost nothing beyond a spectacular potential for misrepresentation.
It would be a mistake to think that what I have said about the prevalence
of teleological, or goal-directed, language in biology is controversial.
Such language is everywhere acknowledged by those eminent biologists who
have taken any time to reflect upon the matter. The widely accepted or
implied view today is that the presence of information and a computer-like
program in
After a long history of agonizing over the problem of teleological language in the life sciences, materialistically inclined biologists embraced this apparent resolution of the problem with great eagerness. One of the twentieth century’s preeminent evolutionary theorists, Ernst Mayr, commented that during an earlier historical period you had to choose between being “a woolly vitalist (finalist or teleologist) or a naïve physicochemical reductionist”. But now, he could gladly report, the responsible biologist need be neither a vitalist nor a reductionist:
An individual who — to use the language of the computer — has been “programmed” can act purposefully . . . The purposive action of an individual, insofar as it is based on the properties of its genetic program . . . is no more or less purposive than the actions of a computer that has been programmed to respond appropriately to various inputs. It is, if I may say so, a purely mechanistic purposiveness (1976, p. 365).
This is the solution I mentioned at the outset: dumb mechanism somehow manifesting wise purpose, courtesy of information and computation. The biologist could finally accept the purposeful organism without shame. François Jacob, who won his Nobel Prize for discoveries in gene regulation, summarized the matter with French flair: “For a long time, the biologist treated teleology as he would a woman he could not do without, but did not care to be seen with in public. The concept of [a computer] programme has made an honest woman of teleology” (1973, pp. 8-9).
The fact is both notorious and undisputed: biologists employ a language heavily laced with references to computer programs, codes, instructions, and information. While philosophers and historians of biology have noticed the many problems posed by the diverse and inconsistent usages, biologists themselves have shown few scruples, and continue to speak “computerese” with abandon. Jacob in his day was hardly shy about it: “The programme is a model borrowed from electronic computers. It equates the genetic material of an egg with the magnetic tape of a computer”. And “everything urges one to compare the logic of heredity to that of a computer. Rarely has a model suggested by a particular epoch proved to be more faithful” (1973, pp. 9, 265).
Mayr was no less unequivocal. “All organisms possess a historically
evolved genetic program, coded in the DNA of the
As usual, if you want an extreme rhetorical flourish that, in its quest for dramatic impact, tends toward the reductio ad absurdum (thereby performing a useful service), Richard Dawkins is most obliging. In the organism, he tells us, “every cell contains a miniature analogue of a computer’s instruction-obeying machinery” (1996, p. 271). But Dawkins’ computational vision is not restricted to such mundane material phenomena as individual organisms. There is, he believes, a river of DNA that “flows through time, not space. It is a river of information, not a river of bones and tissues: a river of abstract instructions for building bodies, not a river of solid bodies themselves. The information passes through bodies and affects them, but it is not affected by them on its way through” (1995, p. 4).
Or, again, “You can, if you wish, think of the genes in all the populations of the world as constituting a giant computer, calculating costs and benefits and currency conversions, with the shifting patterns of gene frequencies doing duty for the shuttling 1s and 0s of an electronic data processor” (1996, p. 72).
And to complete the dizzying flight into highest informational abstraction, capping it off with a remarkable physical image, Dawkins offers this: “It is raining instructions out there; it’s raining programs; it’s raining tree-growing, fluff-spreading, algorithms. That is not a metaphor, it is the plain truth. It couldn’t be any plainer if it were raining floppy disks” (2006, p. 158).
The thoroughly entrenched conviction that in the organism we’re dealing with something like an information-processing machine with an instructional program seems immune to the kind of withering assaults that have been offered over several decades by the likes of Harvard geneticist Richard Lewontin, developmental systems theorist Susan Oyama2, MIT science historian, Evelyn Fox Keller, and many others. But I am not sure the critics have brought forward the most obvious and compelling facts of the case.
How does one produce a programmable medium, such as an integrated circuit?
Today’s computer chips containing integrated circuits require the most extreme precision of manufacturing, and are produced in facilities costing over a billion dollars. High-tech “clean rooms” prevent disastrous contamination by a single speck of dust, while specialized equipment creates discrete, unthinkably minute, and precisely machined pathways in silicon. These pathways are designed for maximum permanence, and any breakdown or leakage from one to another in an operating computer can spell disaster. Busses — communication channels linking different computer components — are also manufactured for physical permanence and consistent, unvarying performance. Moreover, everything is designed to operate in lock-step, marching in strictest obedience to a clock that “ticks” up to billions of times per second. If one or another communication channel were to get its timing wrong by some tiny fraction of a second, chaos would ensue.
There’s much more, but that’s already enough to make a point no one should
ever have had to argue. You simply cannot take a single step in
realistically relating what goes on in an organism to what transpires
during the execution of a computer program. Nothing even approaching the
surgically precise, rigidly excavated, and unvarying silicon grooves of a
computer chip exists anywhere in a living creature. It is
laughable even to imagine, say, a
And it is more than laughable to picture a pathway that can be traversed,
exactly and without “outside” disturbance, billions of times in succession
— let alone traversed as mere electrical pulses lacking the
complexly sculpted, ever diverse and changing molecular structure that
lends specific function to the signaling molecules,
All this metamorphosing substance of the organism, this openness of every
process to its never fully predictable surroundings, makes the idea of
computer-like rules inconceivable. Those who speak of programmed
instructions in the organism are obligated to point at least vaguely to
the sort of reality they have in mind. But there is nothing whatever to
point to.
A living vortex. The “pathways” in the organism, such as
they are, must function within what, at first sight, might easily appear
to be a chaotic whirl of activity and exchange.
We are not dealing here with precise bits of information traveling the right-angled pathways of an unvarying grid, but with the subtleties of significant form and gesture expressing the unique meaning of the moment. In conducting its internal performances, including its genetic performances, the cell looks more like an improvisational acrobatic troupe than a computer executing a program.
It has proven easy for many to forget that information by itself, as conventionally conceived, does not do anything. Genes as mere containers for sequential information are catatonic — hopelessly inadequate to explain life processes. The cell’s doings are what we need to understand, and they couldn’t be less machine-like or program-driven. The noted twentieth-century cell biologist, Paul Weiss, described how
in contrast to a machine, the cell interior is heaving and churning all the time . . . The only thing that remains predictable amidst the erratic stirring of the molecular population of thecytoplasm and its substructures is the overall pattern of dynamics which keeps the component activities in definable bounds of orderly restraints (1973, p. 40).
Here we see the undeniable truth that, at just about every level of observation in the organism, we witness higher-level order in the face of a certain fluidity and seeming disorder at the next lower level. The organelles of a cell retain their functional identity despite the continual churning of their contents and reshaping of their structure, just as the cell retains its identity in the presence of ceaseless remodeling of its organelles, and just as entire tissues and organs flourish despite the ongoing birth and death of individual cells.
Weiss, with his exceptional rigor of observation, deserves to be read closely. The “organism as computer” analogy does not fare well, for example, in light of this remark:
While definite regions of the early embryo are predictably the rudiments for the formation of heart, liver, kidney, brain, etc., the individual fates of the cells derived from those areas are still unsettled. In other words, overall regularity in the gross is attained and maintained not as a mechanical result and a reflection of a corresponding underlying regularity of rigidly stereotyped behavior of the component elements down to the smallest detail, but on the contrary, in spite of a high degree of vagrancy among the latter. (1973, pp. 24-5)
This could hardly be more unlike the computer. Whatever the programmer’s
overall goals may be, they can be achieved only by enlisting low-level,
hardware processes whose staccato military discipline must be maintained
with unvarying, microscopic precision, lest the entire programmatic
operation come to a crashing halt.
Organisms have bodies. Computers, of course, needn’t have
minuscule components and needn’t operate at incomprehensible speeds. They
can be built with parts operating at many different scales, both spatially
and temporally. But this has no bearing on the point I am making about
the necessity for well-defined sequentiality and undisturbed, repeatable
precision. It does, however, point to another problem for the
organism-computer analogy: computers can be built from virtually any
material — just as their essential logic has been contrived from
radio tubes, magnetic cores, silicon wafers, optical disks, and so on.
You can read in the artificial intelligence literature how to build a
computer with a roll of toilet paper as a central functioning part.
It would be nonsensical to think of translating a yak or orangutan into an alternative set of materials in this way. And the reason is instructive: our goal in building computers was to abstract as far as possible away from qualitative, material reality. The primary aim was calculation and manipulation of abstract information rather than appreciation of the qualities and forms of things. Unfortunately — Star Trek fantasies aside — the yak and orangutan, with their highly distinctive ways of being, are not so easily abstracted from their material existence.
The essence of computation lies in a disembodied logic quite indifferent to its physical implementation — a rather odd fact when you set it beside the biologist’s yearning for a materialist science. And certainly it’s a fact impossible to reconcile with the organism’s insistence upon manifesting itself, not as a computable abstraction, but in the living powers of its own flesh and blood.
Decisive as all this may seem, it is only the beginning of troubles. If the organism were modeled after a computer, it would have to be a computer that builds itself — or, rather, grows itself. But no computer functions by growing the organs of its own functioning — that is, by overseeing the growth of its own hardware. It takes but a moment’s reflection to realize that, whatever such growth might entail, it represents fundamental kinds of processes not even imaginable in anything remotely resembling a computer. And this fact of growth is no mere sideshow in the life of organisms.
The issue here has indeed been routinely acknowledged — where “routinely” means “without much thought”. One experiences a kind of mental vertigo upon reading the casual and unexplained remark by Jacob that the organism “determines the production of its own components, that is, the organs which are to execute the programme” (1973, p. 9). Or Mayr’s equally bald assertion that “one of the properties of the genetic program is that it can supervise its own precise replication and that of other living systems such as organelles, cells, and whole organisms . . . it required the rise of computer science before the concept of such a program became reputable” (1982, p. 56).
Embraced by unreflective biologists, perhaps — but reputable? How
does an all-but-unthinkable concept — that of a computer that grows
itself and all its parts even as it operates — become reputable?
Different organisms making common cause. Then, too, there
is the fact of hybridization among organisms — not only among
closely related species, but sometimes among distantly separated ones,
even, in some cases, representatives of different phyla with their
radically different body plans (Ryan 2011). This hybridization
illustrates a life-potential in the organism, a power of adaptation,
mutualism, and self-restructuring, that is again impossible to conceive in
computational terms.
Try this by contrast: take two hugely complex computer programs performing different tasks on different hardware, and then, after arbitrarily deleting significant parts of each program, throw the remaining pieces together in a small bit of novel hardware. Is there any hope that the program fragments will now mutually adapt to each other and operate in concert — will function at all — let alone grow their own hybrid “body”, or hardware?
Actually, it is not only the hybrid organism that exhibits this striking
power of transformation. The offspring of normal sexual reproduction
achieve much the same thing on their own scale. The differing biological
potentials passed on from the two parents are blended in the
If, as usually supposed, the organism’s program is a genetic one, borne by
Before we hear someone reply with a vague reference to “parallel distributed computing”, we need to cease the nonsense and ask for specifics. Exactly what understanding is the computer metaphor supposed to convey? There has been precious little effort to sketch out or justify even the most salient elements of the comparison.
Where, for example, do we find the cell’s program? Most would answer, “In
the DNA”. But, as MIT science historian Evelyn Fox Keller has pointed
out, we might more appropriately think of the “information” in DNA as
data, with the cell’s
Vacuity of the computational metaphor. John Mattick, the
Australian biologist at the forefront of much current research in
epigenetics, argues that
Hard indeed. Perhaps far harder than Mattick himself has realized, with his frequent resort to computational language. What, then, is the point? How could someone with the penetrating insight and profound influence of Ernst Mayr assure us that “There is a strict equivalence of the ‘program’ of the information theorists, and [genetic program] of the biologist” (1992, p. 129)? Where has this equivalence ever been spelled out?
It is common to cite the benefits of a metaphor despite its seriously inappropriate aspects. But in the case of the computer program, I see nothing beyond a combination of vacuity on one hand, and an invitation to misunderstanding on the other. I’ve cited a few of the misunderstandings. As for the vacuity, one might ascribe some sort of value to a general notion of “program”, as in “programs for educational reform”. But “program” in any such broad sense is about as helpful to the biologist as saying, “the organism goes about a certain well-ordered work here”. We know that already. The question is how it does so.
Certainly the organism does accomplish extraordinarily complex tasks. And certainly there are many approximate regularities as it pursues its meaningful and highly directed life. We could hardly expect otherwise. But the leap from this truth to the idea of DNA or the cell or the organism as a programmable medium (analog of Dawkins’ “floppy disk”) is so wildly contrary to everything we know about the organism that it raises questions about the degree to which the biologists making this comparison have even bothered to look at the organism, as opposed to reflecting upon an independent web of long-accumulated and now archaic theoretical constructs plastered over it.
Then, of course, there is the problem of the programmer. In the case of the only programs we know, he or she must stand apart from the programmable medium in order to design its program. When this problem is raised, one routinely hears an appeal to natural selection as the “real” programmer. Yet, far from explaining the presence of programs, natural selection, as conceived by evolutionary theorists, can only be another name for the outcome of competition among many already existing programs. Natural selection assumes the goal-directed activities of organisms, including their drives to sustain their own lives and reproduce. The theory does not explain these activities; it is founded upon them.
I imagine many readers, upon reading Paul Weiss’ reference above to the “heaving and churning” sea of cytoplasm, may have been slightly startled by its antithetical resonance with the earlier remark we heard from Dawkins: “There is no spirit-driven life force, no throbbing, heaving, pullulating, protoplasmic, mystic jelly. Life is just bytes and bytes and bytes of digital information”.
The fact of the matter is that if you leave aside the ridiculing intention of “mystic jelly” and “spirit-driven life force”, what remains of that first sentence gives us a fair, if limited, description of the living cell — pretty much what Weiss, as a meticulous and life-long observer of cells, was routinely describing. But, of course, all Dawkins’ terms were intended to ridicule — which leads one to wonder what sort of problem he has with actual living substance. Perhaps Susan Oyama was on to something when she found herself “smiling at the gross bodily dampness of his imagery” (2009).
One way or another, it’s a dampness Dawkins apparently would prefer to do
without. He yearns, not for the cell’s seminal plasmic seas, teeming with
the unruly forms and movements of molecular life, but for the pure, thin,
clean air of abstraction — not actual chromosomes with their
snaking, coiling, looping dynamism amid all the purposeful turbulence of
the viscous
When, over three years ago, I turned to the technical literature of molecular biology for the first time, I was surprised to find how immediately understandable much of it was. Certainly there were challenges — and a great deal of specialized terminology to master — but I felt strangely at home in the atmosphere and logic of these texts. It took me a while to realize why this was. My background in computer engineering was the key. The papers I was reading were very like the books about computers and software I was so familiar with.
I mentioned this in a brief article a year or two ago. But now I find that my realization had already been given voice fifteen years earlier — by Richard Dawkins. “What is truly revolutionary about molecular biology”, he wrote in River Out of Eden, “is that it has become digital”. We now know that genes “are long strings of pure digital information . . . The machine code of the genes is uncannily computerlike. Apart from differences in jargon, the pages of a molecular-biology journal might be interchanged with those of a computer-engineering journal” (1995, pp. 17-19).
Yes, the computer engineers have conquered molecular biology. I suppose
that science historians of the future will puzzle for many years over the
question, “How could Dawkins and so many of his eminent peers have gotten
it so crazily and unthinkably wrong?” A puzzle indeed. In exchanging the
heaving seas of protoplasm for digital information and programs,
biologists have wandered very far from home.
Curiously, two reputed features of DNA-embedded information have so far
remained largely above criticism, at least by biologists. These features
have to do with the arbitrariness of the informational encoding of
The supposed arbitrariness of DNA (and
Much the same is said to be true of the information-bearing letters of
DNA. It is, we’re told, the instructional logic they carry that really
matters, and the embodiment of this logic in material is as arbitrary as
the embodiment of meanings in English alphabetical sequences. As British
geneticist and evolutionary biologist, John Maynard Smith, remarked: “In
both protein synthesis and in later development, genes are symbols, in
that there is no necessary connection between their form
Maynard Smith’s use of the word “symbol” was part of an explicit
comparison of the letters of the DNA
It would be an entirely different (and healthier) matter if, without assuming such conscious, abstracting powers on the part of our cells, we compared DNA to the forms of language proper — that is, a language capable of expressing something, as in eloquent speech or bodily movement. After all, it is a reasonable assumption that, at every stage of evolution, features of cells and organisms appeared by virtue of their immediately effective role in the larger performance, not because “someone” said, “Let this stand arbitrarily for that”.
As for the second notion — that the information in DNA is digital
— basically, this means it is discontinuous and consists of
discrete, repeatable elements that can be discriminated from each other
unambiguously. Due to this digital nature, the information in every
stretch of the
The arbitrary and the digital come neatly together in the foundational idea of the DNA sequence. The arbitrariness encourages the biologist to think of the sequence as such — to think of mere sequence rather than meaningful form within a larger context of form, much as a low-level programmer can think of a sequence of 0s and 1s without materiality getting in the way. This strictly sequential “information content” of DNA can be detached for analysis quite apart from its full-bodied significance and contextual role within the organism. And then the digital aspect of this now-abstracted sequence feeds the conviction that we’re dealing with the precisely defined elements of an unambiguous computer-like program — a conviction one can read in the literature ad nauseam: “the genomic DNA sequence harbors the regulatory instructions dictating gene expression programs” (Shilatifard and Verrijzer 2011). It is “a set of instructions on how to make” the adult form (Maynard Smith 2000).
So an abstract, almost dematerialized sequence, whose digital content is somehow thought to be separable, as information, from its concrete form, becomes the First Cause and Unmoved Mover of the organism. This is what enables population genetics — that great pillar of evolutionary theory — to concern itself centrally with DNA understood as bare sequence. The sequence has the very great advantage that it can be mathematically characterized, traced down through the generations (like Dawkins’ river of DNA flowing through time), and even simulated in computer programs representing “digital organisms” that have nothing at all to do with living creatures or molecular-level form (Talbott 2007). It is a dream fulfilled for any biologist who wants one-dimensional, rigorous, manipulable data upon which to erect impressive evolutionary theories.
But if we’re looking for an understanding of organisms, the dream of DNA as an arbitrary, digital, one-dimensional, information-bearing sequence is more like a nightmare — one whose hold upon the biologist’s imagination has been fierce and tenacious. The extremely limited truth in the idea relates to reality rather like a series of vertebrae lying in the dust relates to a living, breathing creature.
What we actually see in the cell nucleus are
Removing nucleotide bases from their structured context and making a mere fact of sequential ordering central to our explanation of the organism is rather like making the fixed sequence of keys on a piano the primary basis for explaining the performance of a Mozart piano concerto. It is to ignore the music-making — the qualitatively distinct harmonic relations between the different keys, the way the keys are struck in time, the endless subtlety of touch, the carefully inflected phrasing, the melodic progression and shifting harmonies, the role of all the other players in the orchestra, and, above all, the way the entire performance holds together as a clearly recognizable, aesthetic whole.
But the analogy is a poor one, for, among other things, it ought to show the keyboard itself twisting and looping like the chromosome, morphing into ever new forms, dancing to a music that is really the music of the piano, pianist, and orchestra together — music in which the individual keys of the piano contribute their own fluid notes only as modulated by each other and by a thousand influences from other players in the orchestra.
As our discussion of
The processes of the cell are founded upon an intricacy and complexity and expressiveness of form beyond all current comprehension. It is true — and one of the misdirections of biology in recent decades — that many elements at the molecular level have been conceived as fixed and well-defined, or as “switchable” in a neat, binary way between alternative fixed and well-defined shapes.
But over the past few decades these elements of an overwrought,
computational imagination have consistently and thoroughly been yielding
to deeper insights showing them to be dynamic, variable, thoroughly
contextual, expressed in significant temporal rhythms and spatial
patterns, and fluid in their functioning — all prerequisites for the
integral and unified character of the organism. And all consistent with
the fact that, in living processes, we witness something more like the
meaning of an ongoing story than a computational manipulation of
alphabetical
The element of truth in the conventional view is clearly important when
seen without distortion and when recognized as a high abstraction away
from the living reality. It is that
What is further remarkable about the
“But in any case there are certain regularities in the relation
between DNA sequences and proteins!” Of course there are, just as there
are regularities of grammar and word usage in meaningful speech. But we
do not understand someone’s speaking by attending only to its grammatical
forms. Similarly, the only way to understand what is going on in the
organism is through receptivity to the biological speech in all its
fullness. If only we would cease hiding behind the insupportable idea of
programs and arbitrary
It would be wrong to take me as saying “Our abstracting habits can find nothing like a digital code in DNA”. I am actually saying, “What we have is immeasurably richer than any digital code” — so much so that comparisons to alphabetic codes are hopelessly inadequate. It would be far better to think of human speech, which is, after all, a more living, dynamic production than letters on the printed page.
Yes, we can identify an approximate syntax and certain repeated elements (phonemes) in human speech. But the structure of our speech is plastic, lending itself to expressive intent. The succession of phonemes is related to meaning, but as a mere sequence of idealized elements frozen and excised from the living flow of speech it scarcely begins to impart its significance.
No two speakers pronounce a given phoneme in exactly the same way, and no one speaker pronounces a phoneme identically in different contexts. Volume, inflection, effect of neighboring phonemes, warmth or coldness of feeling, suggestions of willful intent, bodily gestures (extending and complementing the gestures of the vocal apparatus), physical surroundings, immediate social circumstances — all this and much more plays into the nuances of meaning to which we give voice. There are a thousand ways to say the word “stop”, with just as many distinctions of meaning.
If, in fact, the molecular organism presents us, not with a rigid and arbitrary code, but with a true language, a language of meaning, then a great deal of what we know about text and context, about syntax and semantics, enriches our understanding, not only of DNA and RNA, but of all the significant activities of cell and organism. Virtually the entire history of molecular biology since the discovery of the double helix has led us in one direction only: we have had to reckon ever more fully with context-dependence, with plasticity, with dynamism, with interpenetrating layers of meaning (well-directed coordination, regulation, and organization) — all giving voice to the coherent story of the organism’s life.
What has made DNA (along with
Far from yielding itself to the restrictive proprieties of mathematically analyzable information, DNA participates shamelessly in a living story. If meaning, unreduced and therefore “unnaturalized” — meaning that truly informs the organism — is Jacob’s wanton woman, then the organism remains as wonderfully wanton as ever. It is a living agent — a being — weaving a narrative through the expressive gesturings that are the forms and meanings of its incarnated existence.
The genomic sequence as an arbitrary digital construct is an artificial, life-killing imagination projected onto the organism by a science haunted by the fear of vitalism — that is, haunted by life’s meaning, it’s vitality. It’s a science determined to “naturalize” this vitality, as if it represented a threat to the lawful order of things (which it certainly does not). What it does threaten is all conventional, Darwinian interpretations of evolution.
This is presumably why Richard Dawkins made what he may now fear was an unexpectedly significant statement: “Digitalness is probably a necessary precondition for Darwinism itself to work” (2006, p. 163). Certainly it is a precondition for anything like the currently prevailing Darwinism to work. Unfortunately, as molecular biologists are showing so clearly, the precondition is being falsified wholesale.
2. One of the most prescient, multifaceted, and incisive treatments of informational notions in the life sciences was (and still is) Susan Oyama’s 1985 book, revised in 2000: The Ontogeny of Information. While she makes no explicit attempt to lead over from information to meaning (as I do here and in previous articles), much of her work contributes to such a broadening of perspective.
Barfield, Owen (1967). Speaker’s Meaning. Middletown CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Dawkins, Richard (1995). River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life. New York: BasicBooks.
Dawkins, Richard (1996). Climbing Mount Improbable. New York: W. W. Norton.
Dawkins, Richard (2006). The Blind Watchmaker, second edition. New York: W. W. Norton. First edition published in 1986.
Dethoff, Elizabeth A., Jeetender Chugh, Anthony M. Mustoe and Hashim M. Al-Hashimi (2012a). “Functional Complexity and Regulation through RNA Dynamics”, Nature vol. 482 (Feb. 16), pp. 322-30. doi:10.1038/nature10885
Holdrege, Craig (1996). Genetics and the Manipulation of Life: The Forgotten Factor of Context. Hudson NY: Lindisfarne.
Honig, Barry and Remo Rohs (2011). “Flipping Watson and Crick”, Nature vol. 470 (Feb. 24), pp. 472-3.
Jacob, François (1973). The Logic of Life: A History of Heredity, translated by Betty E. Spillmann. New York: Random House. Originally published in French in 1970.
Keller, Evelyn Fox (2001). “Beyond the Gene But Beneath the Skin”, in Oyama 2001, pp. 299-312.
Lavelle, Christophe (2009). “Forces and Torques in the Nucleus: Chromatin under Mechanical Constraints”, Biochemistry and Cell Biology vol. 87, pp. 307-22. doi:10.1139/O08-123
Mattick, John S. (2009). “Has Evolution Learnt How to Learn?” EMBO Reports vol. 10, no. 7, p. 665. doi:10.1038/embor.2009.135
Mattick, John (2010). “John Mattick: From a Hobby to a Genomic Revolution” (interview), Quest vol. 5, no. 1 (Quarter 3), pp. 38-43.
Mattick, John S., Ryan J. Taft and Geoffrey J. Faulkner (2009). “A Global View of Genomic Information: Moving Beyond the Gene and the Master Regulator”, Trends in Genetics vol. 26, no. 1. doi:10.1016/j.tig.2009.11.002
Maynard Smith, John (2000). “The Concept of Information in Biology”, Philosophy of Science vol. 67 (June), pp. 177-94.
Mayr, Ernst (1976). Evolution and the Diversity of Life. Cambridge MA: Belknap/Harvard University Press.
Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Cambridge MA: Belknap/Harvard University Press.
Mayr, Ernst (1992). “The Idea of Teleology”, Journal of the History of Ideas vol. 53, no. 1 (Jan. - Mar.), pp. 117-35.
Oyama, Susan (2000). The Ontogeny of Information, 2nd edition, foreword by Richard C. Lewontin. Durham NC: Duke University Press. First edition published in 1985 by Cambridge University Press.
Oyama, Susan, Paul E. Griffiths and Russell D. Gray, editors (2001). Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Oyama, Susan (2009). “Compromising Positions: The Minding of Matter”, in Mapping the Future of Biology: Evolving Concepts and Theories, edited by A. Barberousse, M. Morange, and T. Pradeu, pp. 27-45. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 266. Springer Science+Business Media B.V.
Rohs, Remo, Sean M. West, Alona Sosinsky et al. (2009). “The Role of DNA Shape in Protein-DNA Recognition”, Nature vol. 461 (Oct. 29), pp. 1248-53. doi:10.1038/nature08473
Ryan, Frank (2011a). The Mystery of Metamorphosis: A Scientific Detective Story. Foreword by Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis. White River Junction VT: Chelsea Green Publishing.
Shilatifard, Ali and Peter Verrijzer (2011). “Chromosomes and Gene Expression Mechanisms: Peeling Away the Many Layers of Transcriptional Control”, Current Opinion in Genetics and Development vol. 21 (April), pp. 121-3. doi:10.1016/j.gde.2011.02.004).
Talbott, Stephen L. (2007). “Ghosts in the Evolutionary Machinery: The Strange, Disembodied Life of Digital Organisms”, The New Atlantis no. 18 (fall), pp. 26-40. Originally published in NetFuture #170 (July 19, 2007). Latest version available at http://thenewatlantis/publications/ghosts-in-the-evolutionary-machinery.
Talbott, Stephen L. (2010). “Getting Over the Code Delusion”, The New Atlantis no. 28 (summer), pp. 3-27. Original version published in NetFuture #179 (Feb. 18, 2010). Available at http://natureinstitute.org/txt/st/mqual/genome_4.htm.
Wahls, Wayne P. and Mari K. Davidson (2011). “DNA Sequence-Mediated, Evolutionarily Rapid Redistribution of Meiotic Recombination Hotspots”, Genetics vol. 189 (Nov.), pp. 685-94. doi:10.1534/genetics.111.134130
Weiss, Paul (1973). The Science of Life: The Living System — A System for Living. Mount Kisco NY: Futura Publishing.
Steve Talbott :: NetFuture #185 :: June 21, 2012